Introduction
I A first approach to the issues
Democracy does not exist in practice. At best
we have what the ancients would have called elective oligarchies with strong
monarchical elements. Most contemporary discussions of democracy assume that
the task of democratic theory is to provide either some justification for these
regimes or some normative guidance for their improvement.1 It is assumed that the state is a necessity of social life. The question
is whether it can be made more democratic. One of my aims is to disprove this
assumption by showing how a polity might function without the centralization of
government that constitutes the state.
There is no denying that social life is
impossible without government. There must be decision-making bodies that
exercise coercive power over groups and individuals. Moreover, the decisions of
governing bodies must be coordinated, and where negotiation fails some
co-ordinating decision must be imposed on them if peace and rationality are to
prevail. But this neither necessitates nor justifies any body possessing a
monopoly of power to decide and enforce decisions about matters of public and
common concern.
For a variety of reasons I begin with
practicalities, though of a very general and abstract sort, rather than with a
theory of human nature or of society or of rights and authority. Discussions of
these latter matters always involve assumptions about what can be done or is
likely to happen. The values we emphasize reflect our hopes and fears and the
experience from which these spring. The very concepts we use in political
theory are bound up with the structuring of our social world by specific social
practices. What human nature is is a matter of what human beings can do. And
what they can do is a matter of what they have ways of doing, individually and
collectively. What rights seem necessary for people to enjoy and what authority
is desirable are a function of needs that take definite shape only in definite
forms of social life. No doubt human nature is neither indefinitely plastic nor
perfectible, but equally certainly what human beings can do remains a matter to
be explored.
There is no well-founded theoretical basis on
which arguments about human nature can resolve our present problems. It is, I
hope to show, both more profitable and more honest to address ourselves
explicitly to practical problems and their solution in the first instance. Here
the constraints are quite specific. Nevertheless, the solution is unlikely to
arise simply from the analysis of the problem. It will call for philosophical
reflection about its desirability as well as for argument for its
practicability. In the long run, however, proposals can be tested only in
political practice, which will judge both their feasibility and desirability.
The main practical problem about democracy is
easily stated: in any fullblooded sense “government of the people, by the
people, for the people” seems impossible in any but the narrowest range of
circumstances. For government by the people to occur the people must make the
decisions that constitute the content of government. But there is no way in
which they can make these decisions, much less make them on a sound basis, when
the decisions involve so many people in so many different ways as do the
decisions involved in legislating and administering in a modern state. This is
not a matter of technical difficulties of communication. Today we can organize
and address assemblies hundreds of times as big as the Greeks could. It would
be possible to provide everybody with the means of listening to debates on any
topic and recording a vote on every issue without their leaving their
armchairs. But people would be reduced to accepting or rejecting proposals.
There is no way in which any significant proportion could participate in
framing them. Aristotle and other ancient critics of democracy argued that it
inevitably degenerated into rule by the orators and ultimately into tyranny.
The bigger and more passive the audience the more that is likely to happen.
Moreover, if the point of democracy is that
good decisions, decisions that reflect the long-term interests of the people,
should be made, it is questionable whether people can know enough to make
rational decisions on the very large range of issues that have to be faced.
This point has nothing to do with the “ignorance of the mob”. It applies
equally well to professional politicians, social scientists or any other
aristocracy. It is an argument against all centralization of decision-making
power whether in an individual, a small group or a mass assembly. Clearly the
force of the difficulty is a function both of the size and complexity of a
society and of the degree to which its affairs are ordered by explicit
administrative decisions, its degree of socialism. Advocates of the market
mechanism have used it as an argument for small government and advocates of
certain kinds of socialism have insisted on it as an argument for small
autonomous communities. I shall argue that both of these solutions to the
problem are unsatisfactory.
Again, there are inherent difficulties in the
vague concept of “the people”. For all those who, from Plato and Aristotle
onwards, have accepted the importance of class power in politics, rule by the
people comes down in practice to rule of the poor over the rich. As long as the
economic system functions to produce control of the means of production by a
few, class differences will persist. The attempt of the “have-nots” to use the
power of government to limit the power of those who control the means of
production must always lead to a situation of self-defeating conflict. If a
market or, more specifically, a capitalist system is to flourish it must be
possible for owners of capital to make long-term investments with a reasonable
probability of profit. Attempts to redistribute income by taxation must either
fail to have any substantial effect or result in lack of investment and
economic hardship for those in need of employment.
Instability produces war and repression.
Ruling groups that are threatened by popular power have always been inclined to
use military means, demagogy and treachery to protect their interests. Only in
a classless society does the notion of the people acquire a genuinely inclusive
extension. In a class society it oscillates between a more general and a more
specific meaning in a way that reflects the contradictory interests of the
different classes. But is a genuinely classless society possible? Is it
possible to avert concentrations of economic power and of status only at the
cost of an intolerably restrictive concentration of political power in the
hands of those who claim to represent the people?
[See, however, my remarks about Marxist class
analysis in the preface to the second edition.]
Moreover, the concept of the people covers up
an enormous variety of differences of interest connected with specific forms of
life and community property. Most significantly, each nation-state treats its
own territory as a collective property subject to no external interference. The
people are always the French or British or Guatemalan people. The “people of
the world” has a hollow ring even in rhetorical contexts. It corresponds to no
operative reality. But many of the problems that we face, ecological, economic
and humane, are soluble only on a global basis and with an eye to the future
needs of all humankind.
If government by the people for the people
can be conceived coherently only as government by all existing human beings in
the long-term interests of the human race and of the world that it dominates,
is it not patently impossible? Would any nation be willing to submit itself to
a world state that would dictate to it how its resources were to be used and
disrupt its way of life to conform to the prescriptions of some remote
majority? How could such a remote and all-powerful body admit of any meaningful
participation by the thousands of millions whom it governed? Can there be world
democracy without a world state?
There is, finally, a fundamental point of
principle that is hardly ever addressed by democratic theorists. It is
desirable that each person or group should have an opportunity for influencing
decisions of any matter in direct proportion to their legitimate material
interest in the outcome. It is not often noticed that this principle is
ineffectual unless its converse is also satisfied. Nobody should have any input
into decision making where they have no legitimate material interest. The
notion of legitimate material interest calls for explication. Roughly, by “material”
I mean to exclude interests that people have simply because of their intrusive
desires about how others should fare, while by “legitimate” I mean to exclude
material interests that are not based on entitlements that are morally sound.
The point of these exclusions is obvious
enough. Individuals or groups do not acquire the sort of interest that entitles
them to have a say in determining what I or some group to which I belong may do
simply by their having strong feelings about the matter. Their interest must
have a more material ground than their thinking about the matter. Equally,
people may have good reason to covet things that I am entitled to, but that
does not give them a legitimate interest in those things. In particular, in
regard to public goods there is often a serious confusion between people’s
legitimate material interest in the opportunity costs of providing some good
for a particular group and their unwarranted claims to determine just what is
good for the group in question. There may be a reasonable argument that the
money should have been spent elsewhere. But if it is allocated to a certain
educational programme, for example, the precise form that programme should take
is a matter on which those who are directly affected by it should normally
decide.
If these principles are not observed the
result is tyranny, perhaps wellintentioned or unobtrusive tyranny, but tyranny
in a strict sense. People are exercising authority over others, without warrant
and without regard to their proper autonomy, by virtue of possessing political
power. All present forms of democracy and all hitherto proposed forms of it not
only permit but encourage such tyranny. The result is that they strain their claims
to be called democracy and their claims to superiority over monarchies and
oligarchies. Normally they become oligarchies that are defensible only on the
grounds that no better alternative is available.
That this degeneration is a normal
consequence of everybody having a say in everything is not difficult to
understand. In a very small and amicable group people may abstain from using
their votes on matters that do not concern them on the basis of a convention
that it is the proper thing to do. The convention may be sustained by
interpersonal relationships. In larger groups it tends to break down.
Vote-trading becomes the key to success. Not to use every opportunity to
extract the maximum return for one’s agreement to vote in a certain way is to
invite defeat at the hands of those who do. The more uninterested one is in the
specific issues the better. It makes it so much easier to trade favours
uninhibitedly. Naturally, one may need to put some sort of face on it, but
usually that of a soundly pragmatic man will do.
What happens in this process is utterly
different from what happens in a genuine exchange of substantive interests. If
each of us quite legitimately has some title to the same thing we shall have to
bargain about what each is willing to trade for the other’s title, or perhaps
submit to arbitration or the toss of a coin. Each of us has some power over the
other, but unless one of us is so poor in entitlements as not to be able to
secure any reasonable set of his or her interests, or is in particularly
desperate need of just this thing, the exchange will normally be fair. The
exchange ceases to be fair when what I get in exchange for my substantive good
is merely release from an arbitrary threat on your part. The obvious case
arises when you threaten to harm me physically unless I hand over what you
want. But any threat to use arbitrarily power that you have to harm me without
substantive cost to yourself is equally obnoxious, whether it is done out of
malice or self-interest, or even paternalism.
Now in any present form of democracy it is
quite usual for it to be necessary to buy the votes of many people who have no
legitimate material interest in the matter in hand in order to meet the
interests of those who do have a genuine interest in it. Electoral democracy
carries this to the point where the “numbers-men”, the power brokers, operating
through political parties and professionally organized lobbies, manipulate
these disposable votes into concentrations of power for their own
aggrandizement. The trick is to buy people’s votes over the whole range of
matters that come up for decision on the basis of committing oneself to some
limited set of promises about the few things that they feel strongly about. To
make matters worse, those strong feelings are often not based on legitimate
material interests. The system is corrupt and corrupting. We do not realize how
badly it functions only because the existing alternatives are worse.
II Functional autonomy
Our task is to disentangle the knot of
assumptions that go to make these difficulties; rejecting some, showing how
others can be dealt with, accepting others. At the risk of being dismissed out
of hand, I shall indicate what my strategy is. I shall argue that most of the
decisions that are now taken by centrally controlled multi-function agencies
ranging from nation-states down to municipalities could be taken by autonomous
specialized agencies that are co-ordinated by negotiation among themselves or, if
that fails, by quasi-judicial arbitration, rather than by direction from a
controlling body. Participation in the decision-making process in each body
should extend not to “the people” generally, but to those who are affected by
the decisions in question to the degree in which they are affected. Obviously,
this raises a crucial problem about what interests are to be accounted
legitimate. Interpreted conservatively it could mean that all existing
interests are to be protected. Interpreted radically, it might seem that
everything is “up for grabs” and every individual or group has an interest in
almost everything. I shall attempt to show how a course might be steered
between these extremes.
The first element of my strategy, then, is
not only anti-state but anticommunalist, directed against giving sovereignty or
anything like it to any geographically or ethnically circumscribed group. In
doing so it runs contrary both to the major tradition of political philosophy
and the course of political history, as well as to most projections for the
future, conservative or radical. Nevertheless, I shall argue that the problems
we have to face in practice can be solved only by moving in the direction of
functional decentralization of this kind. My argument will involve an
examination of the inherent characteristic of the various decision-making
procedures that already exist in social practice designed to demonstrate their
limitations and the effects of using them beyond the scope of those limitations.
In particular, I shall examine the limitations of the market, bureaucracy and
voting as mechanisms for the control of productive resources and argue that
other mechanisms could be introduced in appropriate contexts that would not
have the same limitations.
If the division of communal and corporate
agencies into specialized functional agencies were carried as far as possible,
subject to considerations of technical efficiency, the number of
decision-making bodies with considerable autonomy would be increased
enormously. Even at a municipal level there is no reason why the various
services that local councils provide, roads, parks, libraries, recreation
facilities, building regulations, health services, garbage collection and so
on, should not be run quite independently of each other, with different
geographical circumscriptions and with closer relations to similar services in
other areas than to many other services in their own area. People might come to
see themselves as being part of many diverse social activities and functional
communities rather than any simple inclusive community. Indeed, this is
increasingly the case in modern urban societies. Nevertheless the very
complexity of modern life raises a seemingly intractable practical difficulty.
In most local communities there is little enough interest in local politics. If
people are faced with the need to participate actively in the very large range
of agencies of all shapes and sizes that affect their wellbeing, it seems most
unrealistic to suppose that they can or will do so in an informed and
constructive way. In practice they will vote en bloc for party tickets and hand
over their active voice to political elites.
III Statistical representation
This brings me to the second and more
outrageous element of my strategy. In order to have democracy we must abandon
elections, and in most cases referendums, and revert to the ancient principle
of choosing by lot those who are to hold various public offices.2 Decision-making bodies should be statistically representative of those
affected by their decisions. The illusory control exercised by voting for
representatives has to be replaced by the chance of nominating and being
selected as an active participant in the formulation of decisions. Elections, I
shall argue, inherently breed oligarchies. Democracy is possible only if the
decision-makers are a representative sample of the people concerned. I shall
call a polity based on this principle a demarchy,3 using “democracy” to cover both electoral democracy and demarchy. How
and under what conditions this procedure might work I shall discuss in detail
later. For the moment I shall say just a little about the philosophical
consequences of adopting it.
Until about two hundred years ago it was
widely assumed that the principle of rotation of offices by lot was the
characteristic procedure of democracy.4 Since then democracy has
come to be identified with competitive elections on an universal suffrage. In
practice, this situation has arisen because democratization has usually been
won by a series of steps, each of which has been mainly a matter of bringing
existing political elites under the control of a wider group of the population
by submitting them to the necessity of competing for office at regular
intervals. It has rarely been a major tendency of such changes to widen the
political elites themselves. When new groups have acquired the franchise they
have often sought to generate their own political parties, but the elites that
constitute the ruling stratum in these parties have usually come to be only
superficially distinguishable from the more traditional elites. Elitism has not
been challenged effectively.
In the theory of democracy two quite
different strands of classical liberal theory have contributed to the
identification of democracy with elections. Classical utilitarianism claims
that actions are to be evaluated solely by their consequences. What matters is
that governmental decisions should be good decisions. The responsibility of
decision-makers is not to give people what they want, but what is in their
interest. The role of elections is to give electors the chance of choosing
those who are best equipped to make good decisions, those who possess all the
knowledge and skill that the electors themselves inevitably lack. By contrast,
a less clearly formulated tradition, often associated with Rousseau and more
generally with contractual views of political authority, sees elections
essentially as the expression of the collective will of the electors. The
government derives its legitimacy not from its function or its deeds and their
consequences but from a commission given to it by an agreed procedure of electoral
choice. A governmental agency ought to do all and only those things that the
majority of the electors want it to do.
The utilitarian position about elections
depends primarily on factual considerations. Elections are supposed to be the
best means we have of seeing that government is properly carried on. So my
differences with them will be resolved by the discussion of the possibility and
consequences of statistically representative democracy or demarchy. (I am not a
utilitarian but the differences do not matter in this context.) The contractual
tradition, however, raises more complex questions. One might argue, for
example, that a voluntarist account of political authority is compatible with
any form of government, since the people can will anything that they like. But
the voluntarist view may be pressed so far that only those particular decisions
that command informed, universal and explicit consent are deemed legitimate. In
that case any substantial existing interest group is in a position to block any
change that affects its interests adversely. Even if the requirement of consent
is restricted to decision procedures rather than extended to specific
decisions, no group would consent freely and rationally to decision procedures
that would undermine its vital interests.5
Some contractarians, notably John Rawls, have
held that it is possible to escape the problems of actual interests and to
deduce a set of moral principles of legitimacy from a thought experiment. This
envisages a group of people who are ignorant of what their interests will be
convening to decide on a constitution that will be beneficial to the
contractants no matter what their interests may turn out to be.6 These moral principles would then act as constraints on what could be
deemed a legitimate will. I believe that such hopes of deriving definitive
results from thought experiments are theoretically and practically illusory.
Nevertheless, given some fairly weak assumptions, I believe that the Rawlsian
move constitutes a reasonable test that any proposal calling itself democratic
should pass. I believe that my proposal would pass.
At the other end of the scale from extreme
individualist voluntarist views we come to views that attribute to the
corporate will of the people a more or less mystical rightness. This will is
not the product of compromises between conflicting interests or of accepted
constitutional procedures but of historical necessity or of some Volksgeist. In
so far as it attains concrete expression it is manifested in a charismatic
leader or an organization that claims some unique authority to articulate it
correctly. It is hardly necessary to emphasize either the enormous dangers of
such movements or the ease with which they may in fact constitute a very
effective social force in certain circumstances. One of the salient features of
the sort of polity I am advocating is that it radically undercuts the
possibility of such movements using the instruments of government to force
their will on people. Indeed, I should hope that it would result in the
dissolution of the social basis of charismatic authority and destroy its grip
on people. Even if it is true that many of us have some profound psychological
need for identification of a non-rational kind with some totality that
transcends us, perhaps we can satisfy this need by identifying with football
teams rather than governments, “historic missions” or the destinies of races.
Nevertheless, no profound social change can
take place in a conscious and deliberately controlled way unless there is a
very wide consensus that it is at least acceptable, and a substantial group
that is both strongly motivated and organized to bring it about. I concede that
the central requirement in our present historical situation is that the working
class should become conscious of the need to abolish the sources of class
division at every level of social life. This is especially the case in the
matter of control of the means of production. To that extent I agree with the
classical Marxist analysis. [In fact I now reject a class analysis, stressing
instead conflicts of interest that we all have. In a market society we all have
some interest in the profitability of capital investment and some interest in
the prosperity of people who sell their labour power. It is no longer true in
advanced capitalist societies that most people possess nothing but their labour
power, though there is a significant minority of whom this is true.]
In any case what that analysis lacked in my
view, was a sufficiently rigorous and constructive theory of democratic
government.7 Rather, the classical Marxists tended to share the anarchist
assumption that in the struggle for democracy the revolutionary movement would
generate spontaneously the decision procedures and institutions that were
needed to produce a democratic society. I shall argue that in this respect it
was deeply mistaken and try to indicate the strategies that are appropriate for
a revolutionary socio-political change in a democratic direction.
IV Assumptions
Demarchy, as I shall present it, is utopian,
at least in the sense that no model for it exists, and it is not based on a
projection of present trends or causes. It can be brought about, if at all,
only by convincing enough people that it should be tried. Obviously the chances
of doing that are small. So it is all the more important to emphasize that in
other respects it is not utopian at all. In particular, I shall argue that it
does not presuppose that people perform substantially better either morally or
intellectually than they do at present. My hope is that it could create
conditions that would lead to improvements in the level of moral and scientific
self-awareness in the community through a self-reinforcing process, but there
are good grounds for embracing it without putting any store by such hopes. It
is offered primarily as a solution to present problems, a way of averting very
great evils, starting with small practical steps.
Meanwhile, the lack of any clear and
plausible view of how a democratic socialist society might work is, I believe,
the main obstacle to significant radical activity. State socialism in all its
forms has been discredited. It has become increasingly difficult to put all the
failures down to exogenous causes. The kinds of changes that can be produced by
the use of centralized power are not the changes most socialists had hoped for.
Moreover, popular spontaneous action is clearly no remedy. At best it is
haphazard, illcoordinated, often foolish and shortlived. At worst, it is terror
manipulated by leaders engaged in power struggles. The fond hopes of the
anarchists, which Marx himself and so many Marxists have shared, that the
solutions to how future society is to be governed will emerge in the process of
struggle have proved illusory. Organized struggle to control the state calls
for military and political organization of a centralized and authoritarian
kind. It reproduces state power transferring it into the hands of different
people. Unorganized struggle merely forces the existing power structure to
adapt. It cannot replace that structure.
Still it will appear absurd to many to offer
a few changes in procedure as a solution to the great problems of our time. It
smacks of panaceas and monomanias, like Berkeley’s faith in tar water. Blanket
scepticism, however, is no more rational than credulity. Procedures are very
important, especially where it is a question of producing decisions from a mass
of disparate inputs that can be interrelated in a variety of ways. In order to
produce reliably good quality output a sound procedure is needed both to select
good quality input and to process it properly. In social decision-making the
crucial questions are, What kinds of information about the situation can the
decision process handle? What desires and aspirations does it respond to? How
good is it at coming up with the most practical and appropriate decisions in
the circumstances?
Decisions are made by people. Good people may
arrive at good decisions in spite of poor institutionalized procedures, when
they are not wholly constrained by those procedures. Conversely, the best
procedures in the world can be misused by people who are determined to do so.
But the more complex the society and the longer our time-span the less likely
it is that these divergences from the norm will be significant. This is not
just a matter of probabilities sorting themselves out in the long term. Procedures
have a constraining effect on what is registered and what is made of it, and
the constraints tend to grow tighter the more deeply entrenched the procedures become.
If the success of a business enterprise is entirely a matter of its relative
profitability, then it becomes increasingly difficult for a manager under the
pressure of competition to take account of factors that produce no profit, even
if there are other good reasons for doing so and the cost is not great. The
manager becomes typecast in the role of profit producer. There may even be a
suggestion of impropriety, at least in the eyes of accountants and
shareholders, in stepping out of that role. It is not the manager’s money that
is involved. Similarly, judges are increasingly held to the letter of the law,
bureaucrats to regulations and politicians to what generates the most favourable
balance of power, whatever their personal preferences.
The crucial problem is that our present
procedures of public decisionmaking are incapable of registering reliably a
number of aspects of the situation that are of great concern to those who
understand them, and incapable of drawing reliably the appropriate conclusions
even from the information they do register. Because they deal with vital
questions they must be changed. The change will not be an improvement unless
certain other conditions are present. Above all, there must be enough people
who in their own interests are willing and able to make the changed procedures
work. I shall argue that it is not unrealistic to suppose that there are enough
such people, and that there are practical strategies of change available. A
major point is that nobody is required to participate in the political process,
but just to trust those who do.
Similarly, I shall have to argue that it
would be rational for people to accept the decision procedures I am advocating.
My argument will be that it is much less risky to hand over control of public
goods to a variety of very limited agencies than to one omnicompetent agency.
The risk of irresponsible action is dispersed. Total disaster is less likely.
However, the problem of control becomes more complicated. It is, superficially
at least, much easier to keep a watch over a single authority than over very many.
But the watch one can keep over an omnicompetent authority cannot be very
effective. In any case, on most things that affect me I have no particular
view, certainly no wellfounded basis of assessment. I should be reasonably
content to have those matters looked after by people who are competent,
sensitive to my interests and are watched by others who share my needs. At the
same time, I should like to have the opportunity of playing a substantive role
in those few areas in which I have some stronger interest and knowledge,
provided the benefits of doing so outweigh the costs.
By contrast with existing democratic
practice, demarchy does not assume that most of the population is in a position
to make soundly based assessments of all the major issues of government policy
or even to assess the merits of rival elites competing for votes. What it
assumes is that most people, if they are faced with limited concrete questions
about matters that affect them directly, are capable of gaining enough
understanding of the issues to make sensible choices about them. Moreover, it
is not too difficult to arrange things so that they have sufficient inducements
to act responsibly in these matters, to seek the best advice, open up
discussion of the possibilities and attempt to find optimal solutions. Where
more difficult, higher-level functions are involved, it is more likely that
people with suitable competence and motivation can be found and chosen by and
among those who have worked together on more limited problems than by any other
selection process.
My pessimism about our present political
structures is accompanied by a similar pessimism about our economic structures.
I shall have to show how these too can be changed for the better. Again I shall
argue that, granted reasonably realistic conditions, the crucial factor is the
practices that constitute decision procedures in these matters. I make no
pretensions to solve the problems of economic theory, nor do I draw very much
on the many extensions of economic theory to matters of public choice. All of
this work achieves a certain rigour at the cost of working with very limited
and abstract models. These models can be applied to real situations only with a
good deal of caution, which is often missing in their advocates.
By contrast, the considerations I shall offer
are of a looser, but more practical kind, suggestive and exploratory rather
than theoretical and explanatory. Ultimately, the only solid ground for
asserting that something is possible is that it exists. Conceptual analysis can
show that a state of affairs is conceivable, but it cannot pretend to show that
the conception encompasses everything that is needed for it to be realized. So
it cannot even assure us that a state of affairs is not impossible, much less
that it is possible in some stronger sense, for example possible under certain
given conditions. The strength of conceptual analysis lies in bringing out the
contradictory characteristics of conceptions that at first sight appear quite
reasonable. So I make no sweeping claims about the arguments offered in this
book. They are designed to induce readers to give practical consideration to
certain possibilities in the light of their own needs and experience. My
justification for asking people to read this book is that if what I have to say
is right it is very important, and it has not been said before. It is intended
to provoke and challenge readers of every sort to say where it is wrong.
V The argument
Chapter 1 confronts the usual arguments for
the necessity of the state in an attempt to undermine them, and underlines the
dangers in the state system and the precariousness of attempts to control it.
It is argued that the system of states generates rigidities and absurdities
that are impossible to control democratically. In chapter 2 the problem of
bureaucracy, control from the top through large permanent administrative
organizations, is examined and the reasons for it criticized. The possibility
of organizations being answerable Introduction 13 directly to those affected by
their decisions is explored and the problems of such a system clarified.
Chapter 3 undertakes a sustained critique of
voting, emphasizing the paucity of the information a vote can convey, the
futility of the individual vote in mass assemblies and the impossibility of
voters becoming well informed. The defects of party politics and the incapacity
of reforms in systems of voting to remedy them are detailed. This critique is
followed by an argument that statistically representative decision making
bodies would provide a means of meeting all the major objections to electoral
politics, as well as providing a means of breaking bureaucracies down into
small units under the direct control of those they affect.
Chapter 4, having briefly surveyed the
inadequacy of a pure market economy to provide public goods and reasonable
access for all to the means of production, outlines a proposal for a market
society in which various productive resources are vested in different trustee
bodies. These trustees would be independent of each other and not subject to
any central policymaking or executive body. They would lease productive
resources to firms at prices that would cover the need for public goods, and
safeguard other community requirements. The argument is that demarchy would
constitute an adequate social control of production in a market economy and
provide satisfactory security for all.
In chapter 5 various features of and
objections to this system of public decision-making that I call “demarchy” are
examined, and the hopes that might reasonably be placed in it are detailed.
A reader who is anxious to get to the heart
of the matter might start at chapter 3, or even at the third section of that
chapter, where the working principles of demarchy are outlined, and proceed to
chapters 4 and 5.
I have many ideas about the practical details
of implementing demarchic principles that are not mentioned in this book. To do
so would have been misleading. What I am anxious to produce is a radical
reappraisal of the whole problem of public decision-making. Once people accept
the possibility of demarchy they rapidly find themselves coming up with an
abundance of suggestions about how it might work in practice. It is one of its
great strengths that it makes experimentation in thought and practice
infinitely easier than in state-governed societies. It thrives on diversity.
Notes
1. For a good critical survey of contemporary
theories of democracy see Jack Lively’s Democracy (Oxford, Basil Blackwell:
1975). My work is much indebted to the works of R. A. Dahl, especially A
Preface to Democratic Theory (Chicago, University of Chicago Press: 1956);
Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition (New Haven, Yale University Press:
1971) and Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy: Autonomy vs. Control (New Haven,
Yale University Press: 1982). Dahl has coined the useful term “polyarchy” to designate
the regimes we usually call democratic in Western countries.
2. On ancient democracy see M. J. Finley,
Democracy, Ancient and Modern (London, Chatto and Windus: 1973) and E. S.
Stavely, Greek and Roman Voting and Elections (London, Thames and Hudson:
1972). All officials other than generals were appointed by lot in Athens, and
the business of the assembly was handled and the agenda set by the council of
five hundred, again chosen by lot, working through its smaller executive.
Another place where appointment by lot was used extensively was in early
renaissance Florence. There, however, the proportion of citizens eligible for
office was a good deal smaller than in Athens. The reasoning behind the
preference for sortition was simple and sound. If people had to choose they
would attempt to elect the best candidates. The candidates with upper-class
backgrounds would normally appear superior. The result would be rule by
upper-class people who engaged in demagogy rather than democracy. British
political history nicely illustrates this point. In other Western countries,
where class differences are not so clearly marked and socially respected, the
result of elections is a professional stratum of politicians whose class
connections are more significant than their origins. Of course, it has usually
been taken for granted that democracy is inferior to rule by the best. The
dominant verdict in Western political thought is in favour of electoral
aristocracy.
3. “Demarchy” is an archaic word which Hayek
used to describe the view he advocated in Law, Legislation and Liberty (3
vols., London, Routledge and Kegan Paul: 1973, 1976, 1979). How ever, since he
did not employ it persistently, it has not passed into current use and I feel
justified in attempting to appropriate it.
4. Rousseau still made this assumption about
class societies, though not about classless societies, Social Contract, Book
IV, Chapter 3. To Godwin, however, writing at the end of the eighteenth
century, sortition seemed a merely superstitious practice. The point had been
lost.
5. The complexities of problems of rational
public choice have been studied intensively in recent years. The best survey is
that of D. C. Mueller, Public Choice (Cambridge Surveys of Economic
Literature), (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press: 1979). See also H. Van den
Doel, Democracy and Welfare Economics (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press:
1978).
6. The great exponent of this doctrine is
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press:
1971). There is a very large Introduction 15 literature on Rawls’s work. See
particularly N. Daniels, Reading Rawls (New York, Basic Books: 1974) and Brian
Barry, The Liberal Theory of Justice (Chicago, University of Chicago Press:
1974).
7. Like most nineteenth-century radical
democrats, Marx placed his faith in measures designed to ensure that the
representatives of the electors acted as their delegates. This assumes that the
electors arrive at a well-considered verdict on every important question. I
shall argue that this is unrealistic and inappropriate. Not everybody should
have an equal say on every question. Moreover, the construction of the common
good is a matter of negotiation between different interests, and negotiations
can not be carried out effectively in structures of the kind Marx envisaged. In
general, Marx underestimated the extent to which political structures were
subject to inherent laws quite as constraining as those governing economic
structures. He saw clearly enough the economic absurdities of nineteenth-century
populist radicalism but failed to criticize its political prescriptions. It is
easy to excuse Marx’s oversights in these matters. It is less easy to excuse
his followers, who use the lamest of anti-utopian arguments to absolve
themselves from thinking about politics beyond immediate issues.
John Burnheim, "Introduction" in Burnheim, J.: Is democracy possible? The alternative to electoral democracy. pp 1- 15.